Early societies established private property rights, which individuals recognized reciprocally

By Chris Calton

In Man, Economy, and State, Murray Rothbard expounds the principles of economics by reconstructing an economy from the ground up. Following the practice of classical economists, he opens the book by imagining Robinson Crusoe alone on an island. After identifying the operative laws that apply even to isolated individuals, Rothbard’s second chapter considers Crusoe on an island with one other person, introducing the concept of direct exchange, or the barter economy. In the third and fourth chapters, Rothbard considers the origins of money and prices in an economy of indirect exchange. 

For a treatise on price theory, Rothbard recognizes the need to explain the origins of money prices, as Carl Menger and Ludwig von Mises did before him. In The Theory of Money and Credit, Mises built on Menger’s original explanation for the origin of money by formulating the regression theorem. When considering price changes back through time, Mises theorized that we must naturally come to points of origin and departure.  

“Yale political scientist James C. Scott, for example, notes that evidence for the domestication of plants precedes the formation of the earliest states. He argues states could not exist without a taxable base — grain, most commonly — and the domestication of plants and primitive commerce preceded state formation.”

Paper dollars today have no commodity foundation, but we can easily identify the point at which they were disconnected from specie (money in the form of coins instead of notes). Going further back, we may not be able to empirically identify the moment when specie, or any other commodity, was first used as a form of indirect exchange, but we can logically deduce such a moment must have occurred as primitive economies grew increasingly complex. 

In chapter 2 of Man, Economy, and State, before Rothbard summarizes “Yale political scientist James C. Scott, for example, notes that evidence for the domestication of plants precedes the formation of the earliest states. He argues states could not exist without a taxable base—grain, most commonly—and the domestication of plants and primitive commerce preceded state formation.” Mises’ insights about the origins of money prices, he considers the origins of property rights. With a citation of John Locke, Rothbard asserts the principle of self-ownership and argues that the original appropriation of property comes from mixing labour with yet-unowned resources, such as clearing land for cultivation. Only after establishing a basis for property rights does Rothbard turn to considerations of exchange and money prices. 

Mises recognized that money prices depended on exchange, and he saw the need to explain the origins of monetary exchange. Rothbard took Mises’ idea a step further, recognizing that the prerequisite for market exchange is private property. Therefore, the origin of property norms is just as relevant to economic analysis as the origins of money and monetary exchange. 

“Before we examine the exchange process,” Rothbard writes, “it must be considered that, in order for a person to exchange anything, he must first possess it, or own it.” 

Private property norms must emerge spontaneously.

Critical readers might object how we cannot take it for granted that property rights originate in the way that Rothbard describes. Governments, of course, can establish property rights, even if in violation of Lockean ethics, which adequately provide the conditions for market exchange. But such considerations would be inappropriate for Rothbard’s second chapter, as he is considering an unhampered market economy—one where governments play no role. For markets to exist sans government, private property norms must emerge spontaneously. 

To this last point, Rothbard never asserts that the Lockean rule of first appropriation is the proper means of establishing property rights (though he certainly believed so and made genuinely ethical arguments along those lines in other works, such as The Ethics of Liberty). In Man, Economy, and State, he simply considers the way property norms could logically emerge in an unhampered market.  

Man in a “free, unhampered market...may exchange any type of factor...for any type of factor,” Rothbard writes, but “it is clear that gifts and exchanges as a source of property must eventually be resolved into: self-ownership, appropriation of unused nature-given factors, and production of capital and consumers’ goods, as the ultimate sources of acquiring property in a free economic system.” 

Rothbard’s argument follows a similar logical structure to Mises’ regression theorem, and even extends the continuum of exchange that Mises outlines. When constructing his theorem, Mises views the end point of his analysis as modern monetary prices, and his point of origin is the moment when a commodity is first used as a medium for indirect exchange. Rothbard has the same end point in mind but realizing property rights are necessary for exchange and not a given for any society and, therefore, warrant explaining, he finds the origins of money prices in the original emergence of private property norms. 

Of course, people can provide alternative theories for the origin of private property, but the mere fact that Rothbard recognizes the need to explain property norms is a valuable contribution to economics that continues to go underappreciated. The most obvious objection people might offer to counter Rothbard’s theory is no different than the alternative explanation to Mises’ and Menger’s theories for the origins of money: the state must construct property rights and introduce money, thus creating markets.

“Rothbard finds the origins of money prices in the original emergence of private property norms.”  

Economic exchange preceded the state 

As historians and anthropologists learn more about prehistory (the history of man prior to documentary evidence), the statist theories for both property rights and money crumble. Yale political scientist James C. Scott, for example, notes that evidence for the domestication of plants precedes the formation of the earliest states. He argues states could not exist without a taxable base (grain, most commonly), and the domestication of plants and primitive commerce preceded state formation. Although Scott doesn’t address property rights directly, he notes the formation of early states “required a host of products that originated in other ecological zones: timber, firewood, leather, obsidian, copper, tin, gold and silver, and honey,” which they obtained through long-distance trade of “pottery, cloth, grain, and artisanal products.”  

Recognizing how economic exchange preceded the state, both Rothbard and Mises raised valid considerations for the origins of money, exchange and property norms. In offering their theories, they were engaging in a common exercise among classical economists known as “conjectural history.” In the absence of empirical historical evidence, classical thinkers, such as Adam Smith and Turgot, speculated on the origins of observable, modern institutions based on assumptions about human nature. Although speculative, this method of history was not unscientific. The test of a good theory was that it explained more of what we can observe (both in terms of present society and extant evidence) and omitted less. Historians today who deal with areas of history and have scant documentary evidence, such as Africanists, still engage in conjectural history (even if they may not be aware of its roots in classical political economy). 

In this light, Rothbard’s explanation for the origins of property norms is not a value-laden prescription for how societies should establish private property rights. Instead, Rothbard is recognizing that early societies must have established some system of private property rights, which individuals recognized reciprocally with respect to each other, and he provides a theory for how this system likely emerged. It is not an uncontestable idea (no scientific theory is), but scholars dismissing it as a libertarian sidestep from proper economic analysis fail to understand the important economic contribution Rothbard was actually making.

Chris Calton is an economic historian.

Published in PIPELINE OBSERVER Winter 2022

Pipeline Observer

About

Landowner-driven, CAEPLA advocates on behalf of farmers, ranchers, and other rural landowners to promote safety and environmental protection through respect for your property rights.